CONSTITUTIONAL LAW

E-mail this
Comments
Print Article

Fundamental Right to Reservation: A Rejoinder
by Parmanand Singh*

Cite as : (1995) 3 SCC (Jour) 6


My distinguished colleague Professor M.P. Singh deserves great praise for his incisive analysis of the constitutional issues involved in acknowledging a fundamental right to affirmative action1. Professor Singh maintains that the constitutional scheme as well as judicial decisions support the notion that every member of the Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes can claim preferential treatment as a matter of fundamental right to equality. The great merit of his rights thesis is that it enables the members of the intended beneficiaries to resort to courts to compel the Government to provide compensatory benefits as a matter of right. His paper is particularly interesting in the wake of Mandal 2 according legitimacy and binding power to job reservations for OBCs. It is interesting in this context to note that though he advances several super-classification arguments in favour of the SCs and STs being accorded fundamental rights, he does not seem to have any valid reason not to apply the same arguments in favour of the OBCs as well.

The acknowledgement of a fundamental right to affirmative action deserves our sympathy and support. There is so much of suffering, discrimination and systematic exclusion of members of disadvantaged groups from valued resources, opportunities and careers, that a theory of rights may help them to fight existing inequalities. But despite its usefulness this theory seems illogical, unsound as well as unbalanced. Some may even consider it undesirable. One is aware that the DMK leadership in Tamil Nadu could compel the Government to retain 69 per cent reservation notwithstanding Mandal 2. In Kerala, political compulsions were forcing all the political parties to resist the Centre's directive to eliminate the creamy layer from the OBCs. With too much of politicisation of the reservation issue and political abuse of this device, one has to move with great circumspection in acknowledging a right to reservation. One cannot overlook that Articles 15(4)3 and 16(4)4 have been placed under several limitations especially in respect of a firm evidence of clear and legitimate identification of the backward groups. In Mandal 2 the Court has clearly ruled that reservations in promotions are constitutionally impermissible. The Court has also advised the Government not to make any reservations in higher positions and in specialized areas. For instance, no reservations should be provided in technical posts in research and development institutions, in specialities and superspecialities in Medicine, Engineering and other such areas. Similarly university professorship and higher echelon positions in Defence, Space Science and Nuclear Research have to go by merit alone. Reservations in these kinds of jobs are seen as inconsistent with the values of efficiency that are needed in such professions and services.

The consequences of recognising reservation as a fundamental right are also relevant. Once something which has so far been recognised as a matter of policy is acknowledged as a guaranteed fundamental right, each individual claim to secure the 'enforcement' of such right will be subject only to judicial determination. It may lose popular and political control. The right to affirmative action will thus open a floodgate for indeterminate, uncertain and vacuous claims. It seems even the courts are not likely to be responsive to such claims as a matter of enforceable right. It may be mentioned here that beginning from Balaji5 until the nine-Judge Bench decision of the Supreme Court in Mandal 2, Articles 16(4) and 15(4) have been treated as enabling provisions. In C.A. Rajendran v. Union of India6 it was urged that Article 16(4) was itself a fundamental right granted to the SCs and STs. The Supreme Court rejected it and ruled that this clause imposed a duty on the State to make reservations but "Article 16(4) is an enabling provision and confers a discretionary power on the State to make reservation"7. This proposition was reaffirmed in all subsequent decisions. In 1988, in P & T SCs and STs Employees' Welfare Assn. v. Union of India8 the Supreme Court categorically ruled that it was not open for a member of SCs/STs to move a court to compel the Government to provide job reservations because Article 16(4) was merely an enabling provision. It was, however, held that in providing reservations the Government cannot be allowed to discriminate between SCs/STs of one department with those working in other departments. Finally, in Mandal 2 all the nine Judges uniformly agreed that Articles 16(4) and 15(4) are couched in enabling language and represent an empowerment of the State to pursue the goals of substantive or genuine equality9. None of these Judges even indirectly indicate that these clauses can themselves be construed as aspects of the fundamental right to equality and thus be enforceable in a court of law.

It is submitted that the notion of equality as a matter of policy has to be kept distinct from the notion of equality as a matter of right. Professor Singh forgets that in the Constitution the protective clauses are juxtaposed with the main clauses guaranteeing non-discrimination and equality of opportunity. The Constitution seems to view it as a matter of policy. A policy stipulates a collective goal which a community seeks to pursue. A right is an individual claim which seeks to protect an individual's interest. Rights are primarily protective. They guarantee citizens certain basic freedoms and protect them against intrusion, discrimination and arbitrary action by the State. The duties correlative with these personal rights are largely prohibitions. Constitutional rights inhere in citizens generally and no one is excluded from the benefits they confer. Indeed, these constitutional rights can justly be suppressed for achieving certain social or collective goals. In a sense, Articles 16(4) and 15(4) could be treated as 'authorising' norms in Kelsenian sense, justifying encroachment of the individual's right to equality for achieving real equality for the members of the disadvantaged groups.

Professor Singh is right when he observes: "Discrimination results only when religion, race, caste, sex or place of birth or any of them is made the basis of disrespect, contempt or prejudice for difference in treatment"10. This is exactly the principle that Professor Ronald Dworkin has advanced in defence of affirmative action programmes for blacks in America11. Professor Dworkin holds that rights are individual claims which operate as 'trumps' over collective goals. If a right is truly a right, it must have some weight to 'trump' policy considerations. But compensatory discrimination is thought of as serving a policy of increasing caste harmony by eliminating visible and institutionalised prejudices and increasing economic equality by removing some of the obstacles that keep the members of backward classes in an economically and socially disadvantaged position. Dworkin argues that a right is a matter of principle and thus every citizen has a right not to be discriminated against on racial grounds and has a right to be treated with equal concern and respect. It is submitted that the underlying argument in Dworkin's theory has adequately been embodied in the non-discrimination clauses of Articles 15 and 16. The rights theory of Professor Dworkin may help Professor Singh in justifying preferential treatment but not for justifying a fundamental right to reservation. The justification debate that takes place in America is of little relevance in India in view of a clear constitutional policy of compensatory discrimination as signified by Articles 15(4) and 16(4)12.

The main argument advanced by Professor Singh in defence of his rights thesis is that since Articles 16(4) and 15(4) are no more treated as exceptions to the rest of the provisions, they themselves are fundamental rights. Surprisingly, Professor Singh dismisses the characterisation of these clauses as exceptions in pre-Thomas13 cases as mere 'impressions' gathered on a plain reading of these clauses14. But how can one eat the words used in these clauses just to support a particular theory of rights? The words "Nothing in this article shall prevent the State from making any provision" in Article 16(4) and "Nothing in Article 15 or Article 29(2) shall prevent the State from making any special provision" in Article 15(4) clearly establish that these clauses constitute authorising provisions for implementing the directives contained in Article 46. Whereas Article 15(4) empowers the State to pursue all kinds of equalising measures in all its dealings Article 16(4) is limited only to the device of reservations. Exceptional character of Article 15(4) was noted in Balaji as against excessive reservations and as against public interest involved in preserving and maintaining efficiency in professional and technical education. A percentage limitation was indicated as a broad policy to strike a reasonable balance between the individual claims of meritocracy and collective claims based upon redressal of historic wrongs. This position remains unchanged even after Mandal. It is true, that in Thomas, the Supreme Court ruled that Article 16(4) was not an exception to Article 16(1) but an emphatic statement that equality of opportunity could be carried to the extent of making reservations. But Thomas nowhere acknowledges a fundamental right to affirmative action.

It is respectfully submitted that the significance of Thomas lies in the enlargement of the power of the State to provide employment preferences of all kinds to the members of SCs and STs in view of their special mention in Articles 46 and 335. The State power is not limited only to reservations as a means of preference but the Government can legitimately employ all possible methods to achieve actual or substantive equality for these groups in the services. All other kinds of preferences could be upheld under Article 16(1). Mandal departs from Thomas on this point and adopts the dissenting opinion of Justice Beg in Thomas and expands the meaning of reservation used in Article 16(4) to align the doctrine with existing practice about age relaxations, age waivers, test exemptions, fee concessions and so forth. Clearly Mandal rejects Thomas that Article 16(1) itself mandates substantive equality for the backward classes. Mandal holds that no preferences for these groups will be constitutionally permissible under Article 16(1). Article 16(4) exhausts all power of backward class preferences. In a sense, therefore, Article 16(4) has been recognised as an exception to Article 16(1) in relation to backward classes. In any case whether Articles 15(4) or 16(4) are treated as exceptions or not would be relevant only in discussing the limits of the power of the State to take affirmative action and would in no way help Professor Singh to construct a theory of right to reservations.

Another argument advanced by the learned scholar is that if Article 21 which is couched in negative terms can give rise to positive rights, there is no reason why Articles 16(4) or 15(4) should not give rise to positive rights. He particularly cites Unni Krishnan15 which recognises right to education as an aspect of right to life under Article 21. This argument though attractive is unrealistic. I presume that if pressed, Professor Singh would agree that despite the fact that the directive principles have greatly been exalted in constitutional dignity by an imaginative judicial interpretation according certain directive principles the the status of fundamental rights, the "directive principles as fundamental rights" theory is far from being clear from jurisprudential point of view. It is futile to hold that Article 21 embraces all graces of human civilisation and embodies right to education, right to means of livelihood, shelter, human dignity and a horde of other social goods and then to hold that the realisation of these rights would depend upon the economic capacity and development of the State. If these moral rights have already been recognised as directive principles; then what is the difference? Even these new positive rights enunciated as legal rights do not break the pattern of State patronage and dependence and the passivity of the intended beneficiaries. The implication is that these positive claims can only be 'promoted' and are possibly incapable of being 'enforced' by affirmative litigation. Professor Singh himself seems to assign to Articles 15(4) and 16(4) the status of these positive claims only because he tries to equate the rights in them in the positive claims identified in Unni Krishnan.16

It is important to remember that the courts are involved in a series of contradictions when they are asked to enforce the beneficial rights promised by them. To take just one example, the ambiguity and uncertainty over the meaning of "right to life" as including right to work and means of livelihood enunciated in Olga Tellis17 has led Justice P.B. Sawant in D.D. Employees' Union18 to remark: "This country has so far not found it feasible to incorporate the right to livelihood as a fundamental right in the Constitution. This is because the country has so far not attained the capacity to guarantee it. Advisedly therefore, it has been placed in the Chapter on Directive Principles." Again, in Mohini Jain19, the Supreme Court read a fundamental right to education as an aspect of the right to life and then in the next breath added that meaningful realisation of this right would depend on the economic capacity and development of the State. In Unni Krishnan15 the Supreme Court quickly realised that the prevailing political economy in India could not sustain a fundamental right to education at all levels and then limited the right to education up to the level of primary education. The point is that since most of the reconceptualised beneficial rights do not promise enforcement through judicial process their status is no better than the Directive Principles of State Policy. Therefore, Professor Singh's contention that right to affirmative action should be aligned with other beneficial rights read by the courts in the Constitution is devoid of any merit.

We agree with Professor Singh that the idea of correlativity between rights and duties is a controversial one, at least in the area of constitutional rights. Hohfeld thought of rights (i.e. claims, powers, liberties, immunities) against specific persons and not against the State. But social or economic rights can exist even if they are inadequately protected or enforced through courts. Likewise, the value of equality can be protected by promulgation of constitutional policies and goals. The Indian Constitution imposes an obligation on the State to pursue the goals of substantive equality on the guidelines indicated by the directive principles contained in Articles 38 and 46. Performance of this obligation has been facilitated by Articles 15(4) and 16(4) which explicitly permit the State to depart from formal equality in distributing opportunities and careers in the society. These clauses in effect support the argument of Professor Ronald Dworkin when he asserts: "Government must not only treat people with concern and respect but with equal concern and respect. It must not distribute goods or opportunities unequally on the ground that some citizens are entitled to more because they are worthy of more concern."20 The policy of reservation creates an obligation on the State to treat everyone with equal respect and concern and in this sense this policy serves the principle of equal treatment. But this policy does not create any corresponding individual right in favour of the members of the beneficiary groups.

Asserting a right is quite different from suggesting that something would be on the whole desirable or good. Rights have special normative force. This special normative force is the result of invoking rules that we already accept and are committed to, rather than simply appealing to general moral considerations. If people are to claim 'rights' (like right to reservation) that are not recognised or conferred by any positive or actually accepted rules, their claims are vacuous. Only if we restrict the idea of rights to rights conferred by positive rules can the concept of a right have any definite content and value. In our submission, the claims advanced in the guise of right to reservation should be accepted as social or collective goals or as matters of policy rather than acknowledged as fundamental rights. In short, Professor Singh's thesis reading fundamental right to reservation in Articles 15(4) and 16(4) is highly controversial and problematic even from the point of view of legal as well as social justice.

* Professor of Law, University of Delhi. Return to Text

  1. M.P. Singh : "Are Articles 16(4) or 15(4) Fundamental Rights?" (1994) 3 SCC (Jour) 31-41. Return to Text
  2. Indra Sawhney v. Union of India, 1992 Supp (3) SCC 217. Return to Text
  3. Article 15 deals with prohibition of discrimination on grounds of religion, race, caste, sex or place of birth and states as follows:
      (1) The State shall not discriminate against any citizen on grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex, place of birth or any of them.
      (2) No citizen shall, on grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex, place of birth or any of them be subject to any disability, liability, restriction or condition with regard to:
          (a) access to shops, public restaurants, hotels and places of public entertainment; or
          (b) the use of wells, tanks, bathing ghats, roads and places of public resort maintained wholly or partly out of State funds or dedicated to the use of the general public.
      (3)***
    (4) Nothing in this article or in clause (2) of Article 29 shall prevent the State from making any special provision for the advancement of any socially and educationally backward classes of citizens or for the Scheduled Castes and the Scheduled Tribes. Return to Text
  4. Article 16 deals with equality of opportunity in matters of public employment and reads as follows:
      (1) There shall be equality of opportunity for all citizens in matters relating to employment or appointment to any office under the State.
      (2) No citizen shall, on grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex, descent, place of birth, residence or any of them, be ineligible for, or discriminated against in respect of, any employment or office under the State.
      (3)***
      (4) Nothing in this article shall prevent the State from making any provision for the reservation of appointments or posts in favour of any backward classes of citizens which, in the opinion of the State, is not adequately represented in the services under the State.
      (5)***
      Return to Text
  5. M.R. Balaji v. State of Mysore, AIR 1963 SC 649. Return to Text
  6. AIR 1968 SC 507. Return to Text
  7. Id. 513. Return to Text
  8. (1988) 4 SCC 147. Return to Text
  9. In Indra Sawhney v. Union of India, 1992 Supp (3) SCC 217, Pandian, J. describes Article 16(4) "a matter of policy of the Government", (para 178); Thommen, J. treats it as "an enabling provision conferring a discretionary power on the State". (para 287); R.M. Sahai, J. says that "Article 16(1) is a fundamental right whereas Article 16(4) is an obligation of the State. The former is enforceable in a court of law whereas the latter is not a 'constitutional compulsion' but an enabling provision". (para 564); Kuldip Singh, J. also treats this clause as an enabling one in para 358. Sawant, J. observes: "(T)he provision of Article 16(4) is couched in an enabling language" (para 435) and Jeevan Reddy, M.H. Kania, M.N. Venkatachaliah and A.M. Ahmadi, JJ. also describe this clause as empowering the State to provide job reservations. Return to Text
  10. (1994) 3 SCC (Jour) 31, 36. Return to Text
  11. Ronald Dworkin: "Taking Rights Seriously", 227, 228, 273 (1977). Return to Text
  12. While defending the programmes of privileged admissions on the touchstone of equal protection guarantee Professor Dworkin himself concedes it as a policy when he says "the fairness and constitutionality of any admission program ... is justified if it serves a proper policy that respects the rights of all members of the community to be treated as equals". See Ronald Dworkin: "Taking Rights Seriously" at p. 239. Return to Text
  13. State of Kerala v. N.M. Thomas, (1976) 2 SCC 310. Return to Text
  14. (1994) 3 SCC (Jour) 31, 34. Return to Text
  15. Unni Krishnan v. State of A.P., (1993) 1 SCC 645. Return to Text
  16. Supra n. 1 at p. 37 he observes "If a negative and amorphous right to life and liberty in Article 21 can give birth to new and until recently, unimaginable fundamental rights in terms of the directive principles there is a much stronger case for recognising fundamental rights for the SCs and STs under the positive and quite specific provisions of Articles 15(4) and 16(4)." Return to Text
  17. Olga Tellis v. Bombay Municipal Corpn., (1985) 3 SCC 545. Return to Text
  18. Delhi Development Horticulture Employees' Union v. Delhi Admn., (1992) 4 SCC 99. Return to Text
  19. Mohini Jain v. State of Karnataka, (1992) 3 SCC 666. Return to Text
  20. Ronald Dworkin: "Taking Rights Seriously", at pp. 272-273.Return to Text
Search On Page:


Enter Search Word:

  Search Archives
  Search Case-Law
  Search Bookstore
  Search All


Archives of SCC Articles
Archives
  Subjectwise Listing of Articles
  Chronological Listing of Articles
  Articles Exclusively on the Internet
  More Articles...

Most Accessed Articles
Recent Articles